Sancrucensis

Pater Edmund Waldstein's Blog


Amoris Lætitia

Preliminary Remarks on Religious Submission to Magisterial Teaching

Before turning to Amoris Laetitia I want to first give some general remarks on submission to Church teaching. I recently read Daniel Schwindt’s excellent overview of Catholic Social Teaching, and application of it to the American situation,  The Papist’s Guide to America. Schwindt’s book is notable for its rich account of the common good, making use of Fr. Sebastian Walshe’s profound dissertation on the subject. It is also notable for the exemplary spirit of docility to papal teaching that it displays. Schwindt offers a devasting critique of the rule of private judgement typical of a liberal age, which has infected even many in the Church. And gives a resounding plea for submission to the teachings of the Roman pontiffs, a plea worthy of a Cardinal Manning.

There has been a lamentable tendency in Catholic theology since about July of 1968 to minimalize the requirements of submission to the teachings of the popes. Submission, so goes the argument, is only absolutely necessary to infallible teachings, and according to Vatican I the pope is only infallible under four conditions: “when, (1) in the exercise of his office as shepherd and teacher of all Christians, (2) in virtue of his supreme apostolic authority, (3) he defines a doctrine concerning faith or morals (4) to be held by the whole Church.” Many Catholic theologians, especially in Germany, have argued that these conditions are only met in solemn definitions, in which the supreme pontiff exercises his extraordinary magisterium. This was the strategy adopted by those who wished to dissent from the teaching on artificial contraception of the encyclical Humanae Vitae. This extremely minimalistic approach to the teachings of the supreme pontiffs has always been particularly abhorrent to me. The pope is infallible not only in his extraordinary magisterium, but also his ordinary and universal magisterium, when he intends to bind the Church definitively. Moreover, the Church requires religious submission of will and intellect even non-definitive teachings. My tendency has thus always been to the opposite extreme. And yet, this too can be taken too far.

There are different levels of authoritative teaching, and the require different kinds of assent. In the Professio Fideiwhich I made before my ordination, three kinds teaching are laid out, which each require a different kind of assent:

  1. With firm faith, I also believe everything contained in the word of God, whether written or handed down in Tradition, which the Church, either by a solemn judgment or by the ordinary and universal Magisterium, sets forth to be believed as divinely revealed.
  2. I also firmly accept and hold each and everything definitively proposed by the Church regarding teaching on faith and morals.
  3. Moreover, I adhere with religious submission of will and intellect to the teachings which either the Roman Pontiff or the College of Bishops enunciate when they exercise their authentic Magisterium, even if they do not intend to proclaim these teachings by a definitive act.

The first kind of assent is the assent of divine faith, which has as its object those truths which are revealed by God in scripture and unwritten tradition. This assent has absolute certainty that rests on the veracity of God Himself. The second kind has as its object infallible teachings of the Church, and is therefore unconditional and certain. But the most delicate case is the third kind, which are teachings that are not infallible, and which therefore might be erroneous. Even this third kind requires submission of will and intellect, but such submission cannot be unconditional and absolutely certain as in the other cases. Fr. Chad Ripperfer, in his helpful pamphlet on magisterial authority, quotes the Tanquerrey as follows:

One is not certainly bound, therefore, to these declarations to assent of faith, but internal and religious which we establish by legitimate ecclesiastical authority; nor [is it] absolute assent, since the decrees are not infallible, but prudential and conditioned, so far as presumption rests with the superior in matters of faith and morals. (Tanquerrey, Synopsis Theologiae Dogmaticae, vol. 1, p. 571, n. 844; cited in Ripperger, Magisterial Authority, p. 35)

That is, the third kind of assent is not always given, but it is usually given, since one presumes that the legitimate ecclesiastical authority teaches reliably. The one exception is when a teaching contradicts more authoritative teachings of the Church. The assent is thus conditioned on the teaching not contradicting more authoritative teaching. Note that this is quite different from the carte blanche claimed by German theologians for rejecting non-infallible teachings that are not in accord with their private theological opinions. The exception here has to do with the tradition to which the whole Church, including her rulers, are bound. Thus Fr. Ripperger writes:

[In] the normal course of things one should simply follow the Magisterium. But the Church Herself recognizes by discussing the different kind of assent that there are occasion in which a particular member of the Magisterium will teach things contrary to the faith. (Ripperger, Magisterial Authority, p. 39)

If possible, when one finds a pope  teaching something apparently contrary to more authoritative teaching, one ought to give a reverential reading, interpreting the new teaching in such a way as to make it fit with the old. But this is not always possible. Thus Fr. Ripperger writes:

As a matter of piety, one ought to try to reconcile teachings of various popes. This does not require us to set aside reason when such statements are clearly contradictory and assert that they have continuity. (Ripperger, Magisterial Authority, p. 24)

Something analagous to what I have said about submission to the popes as supreme teachers in the Church applies to their prudential decisions as supreme rulers of her. One is bound in obedience to official commands and legislation of the pope, and for the most part one can presume that his prudential decisions are sound, but one is not bound in every case to “save the appearances” and invent reasons for evidently imprudent actions.

For the most part, I think that Schwindt’s book is successful in avoiding an extreme maximalism. There are, however, a few points where glosses over tensions between different magisterial documents, or gives strained defenses of the prudence of certain ecclesiastical policies. For instance, he quotes Centessimus Annus on the universal destination of goods (“Christian tradition has never upheld this right [private property] as absolute and untouchable. On the contrary, it has always understood this right within the broader context of the right common to all to use the goods of the whole of creation.”), but glosses over the fact that Rerum Novarum seems to say the opposite (“private ownership must be held sacred and inviolable”). (Ernest Fortin has an excellent paper on this problem).

In his discussion of Vatican II, Schwindt defends the prudence of its approach on the following grounds:

The Church is an expert in humanity. She is its physician, and a responsible physician, if he senses the danger of disease or infection, does everything he can to warn his patient of the threat. Ideally speaking, his advice will be heeded (he is the expert, after all) and the patient’s health will be maintained. But sometimes, as we all know from our own experiences, the patient disregards his doctor’s advice and contracts the disease in spite of the efforts of his advisor. In this case and at this point, his doctor will accept this change in conditions and readjust his treatment. We would call him obstinate, ineffective, and even unwise if he did not make this change, for the disease has now set in and this requires advice of a different kind. The patient is diseased. The physician must treat him accordingly, and no amount of lecture about what he could have done to prevent the infection will be of any use to anyone: that course is not currently open to either party. (Schwindt, The Papist’s Guide to America, pp. 48-49).

Thus, Schwindt argues, the popes of the Pian Age tried to warn the world of the threat of liberal opinions, trying to preserve what was left of the health of Christian society. But at the Council the Church was faced with a world entirely infected by liberalism, and so it modified its treatment. I think that while there is some truth to this argument it is simplistic and overly optimistic. I would argue that the ecclesiastical strategy adopted by Vatican II was in fact not entirely prudent, and based partly on a false assessment of the situation of the patient.

Now, at last, I can turn to Amoris Laetitia. It would be easy to give an explanation of the apparent differences between Amoris Laetitia, and previous documents of the teaching Church along the lines of Schwindt’s defense of Vatican II. In a world so thoroughly corrupted by the sexual revolution, different medication is needed to start a recovery, than was used by Paul VI (for instance) who was still trying to prevent a full infection. Again, I think there might be some truth to such a defense. But again it is too optimistic and simplistic. I think that Amoris Laetitia’s approach is in many ways thoroughly imprudent. Moreover, it makes numerous statements that appear on an unstrained reading to contradict more authoritative teachings of the Church. It appears thus to me that we have with respect to certain propositions in Amoris Laetitia the exceptional case outlined above in which assent of mind and will cannot be given, because the propositions (taken in their natural sense) appear to contradict the Tradition.

I had thought of writing the Holy Father directly about my concerns with Amoris Laetitia, but in the end decided to write Cardinal Schönborn instead. The Holy Father chose Cardinal Schönborn as an official interpreter of Amoris Laetitia, and obviously trusts him. It was easier for me to write Cardinal Schönborn, since he is my own bishop, and I know him personally. As Dominican and a close student of St. Thomas his theological background is closer to mine. And he would be better able to explain my concerns to the Holy Father than I would myself. I reproduce the main body of my letter to Cardinal Schönborn below, omitting the first part, in which I discussed magisterial authority.


Excerpt from a letter to Cardinal Schönborn

I want to emphasize at the outset that I am in deep sympathy with most of Amoris Laetitia, and am grateful for its main teachings, which are beautiful and important. But I think that its most important and inspiring teachings are contre-carred by the sections with which I cannot agree.

I think the Holy Father’s concern that Catholic morality is about the attraction of the good, and of true happiness is very good and important. It is absolutely necessary to resist Pharisaical legalism and the Kantian ethics of duty, and to motivate ourselves, and those entrusted to us, by trying to see ever more the goodness of God’s plan, and allowing that goodness to draw us with its attractive power toward partial happiness in this life, and the fullness of happiness in the life to come. As you said in your presentation, this is a very Thomistic concern. I am truly grateful to the Holy Father for emphasizing this truth.

But then there are elements of the document that run against this main thrust— even ones that seem to be motivated by it.

As we know, there are acts which are in virtue of their very objects incompatible with having God as our final end— acts by which we implicitly say “my happiness is not to be found in God.” Such acts are thus totally incompatible with our happiness— even with happiness in this mortal life, which they destroy by depriving us of interior peace, and the friendship with God that we desire in the depths of our being, but they are especially incompatible with the complete happiness of eternal life. Every time that we commit a mortal sin we implicitly deny God. As Blessed Columba Marmion once put it: “Sin is… the negation by the creature of the existence of God, of His truth, His sovereignty, His holiness, His goodness… In voluntarily performing an action contrary to God’s will [the soul] practically denies that God is supreme goodness worthy of being preferred to all that is not Himself; it puts God beneath the creature.

Of course the Holy Father is quite right that grave matter is not the only condition for mortal sin: there must also be full knowledge and deliberate consent. But I think that he seriously underestimates the power of conscience. It is possible for conscience in the sense of the particular judgment about what is good to be in error. It is even possible to be habitually in error about the moral good. But there is something indelible about conscience in the sense of synderesis, the knowledge of the good that God has inscribed in our hearts. Hence moral error always includes an element of “suppressing the truth” (cf. Romans 1:18) that gives witness against us in the depths of the soul.

Now, when someone is living in objective contradiction to the demands of conscience, they are liable to project the internal unrest of conscience on others, and say that others are “condemning” them. It seems to me that Amoris Laetitia misses that point. It speaks much about how the Church should not condemn people, not throw the law at people like a stone, using the confessional as a “torture chamber” etc. Fair enough. But I certainly do not think that that is the main problem with which we are struggling. I do not think that most priests today, especially here in Austria, are inclined to be overly condemning of the lives of persons who do not live according to the truth of marriage. When people project the internal witness of conscience onto the Church, and accuse her of being “unmerciful,” the last thing that they need is for pastors to agree with them that the “rule” is ummerciful, or doesn’t fit their situation, and that they are probably in a state of grace. As most of us probably know from personal experience (I certainly do), when one is being made uneasy by conscience one is eager to snatch at excuses to “prove” to oneself that everything is really OK. It is very dangerous for pastors to help people find such excuses. In the long run such excuses make them miserable in this life, and endanger their immortal souls. Yes, it is necessary to discern the subjective level of guilt— especially with regard to concrete acts in the past for which one has now to give a penance (for example)— but it is highly foolish and counter-productive to predict a low level of subjective guilt for objectively evil actions that someone is intending to perform in the future. If someone comes to me in the confessional and says that they are intending to continue committing objectively adulterous acts, then it is worse than useless to tell them that they will probably not be guilty of mortal sin in doing so, that mitigating factors will probably remove full knowledge or deliberate consent. What such a person needs is clarity to help them to come to repentance.

But what does the Holy Father say? At one point he says the following: “many people, knowing and accepting the possibility of living ‘as brothers and sisters’ which the Church offers them, point out that if certain expressions of intimacy are lacking, ‘it often happens that faithfulness is endangered and the good of the children suffers’” (AL, Footnote 329). This is the sort of excuse that I hear often in the confessional. In my experience the worst response to such excuses is prevarication or circumlocution. What they need to hear in all clarity is that one can never do an intrinsically evil action that good might come. Recently someone gave this very excuse in confession, and I hesitated a bit before replying, but when with some trepidation I gave her a clear response she was very grateful— it was really a moment of grace. The Holy Father does not explicitly agree with the above excuse, but certainly the natural impression that one receives from the way he cites it seems to be that he agrees, and I am afraid that this is how people looking for excuses will take it.

At another point he writes: “A subject may know full well the rule, yet have great difficulty in understanding ‘its inherent values’, or be in a concrete situation which does not allow him or her to act differently and decide otherwise without further sin” (AL, ¶ 301). Again, one can say this about certain definite acts in the past, but when someone is contemplating their whole future way of life it is most dangerous to say something like this. We know that it is never necessary to do an act that it intrinsically evil; God always gives us a way out. Of course, one can foresee that it is likely that one will fall into a sin that has become habitual in a certain situation, but one can never intend to continue to commit acts that are objectively evil. How is it possible for someone in such a situation to sincerely seek God as their last end, highest good, and greatest happiness? One need only apply this way of reasoning to other kinds of sin to see how absurd it is. The Holy Father has been very eloquent in his condemnation of sins against the poor. Consider the case of a priest who would say to a capitalist, who denies his workers their just wage, “you are probably in a state of grace since, although you know the demands of the Gospel, you are not able to understand its inherent values.” What would the Holy Father say to such a priest? He would be horrified, and quite rightly so. Such a priest should say what the Holy Father himself says: “by closing your heart to the poor you are plunging into the eternal abyss of solitude which is Hell” (cf. Pope Francis, Message for Lent 2016). This is what people who are intending to live a life of continual adultery need to hear as well.

So I think that to say that persons who know the demands of the Gospel can intend to continue performing acts gravely contrary to it without mortally sinning is to deny such persons their dignity as moral agents, to deny the power of synderesis in their hearts, and to give them an excuse to make themselves miserable in this life and the life to come.

There were other things that saddened me in Amoris Laetitia, but I will not weary you with a list. I do, however, want to mention two more things. The first is the emphasis that the Holy Father puts on affirming the good elements to be found in “irregular situations:” the impression that one takes from his way of speaking is that all human relations are a mixture of good and bad, and that there is not much difference between a valid Christian marriage, and a so-called “second marriage” that is in contradiction to a valid marriage. But the difference is as great as light and darkness. Persons trying to live a valid marriage, however often they may fall short, are living a sign of Christ’s fidelity toward his Church. But people in an objectively adulterous union are living a lie. In ¶298, Pope Francis speaks of “second unions” as showing “proven fidelity” and “generous self giving.” I do not think that this is a helpful way of talking. Of course evil is always parasitic on good; the only thing that exists is the good, and so in every situation one will be able to find much good. But, as Dionysius says, in a passage often cited by St Thomas, good simpliciter comes from a complete cause, whereas evil (said without qualification) results from any defect. A good way of life is one that is ordered to God as the final end, and any serious lack of conformity to the order that God has established in His creation is enough to make a way of life evil simpliciter— however much it may resemble a good life in detail. A life of continual adultery cannot be ordered to God as its final end, and thus the generosity and the likeness of fidelity that can be found in such a union cannot make the union itself pleasing to God, anymore than the courage and loyalty shown by a Mafioso could make a life of continual theft and murder pleasing to God.

One last point that I want to mention: I was shocked in reading the section on “The family in the documents of the Church” to see that the Holy Father began a chronological overview with Vatican II! One of the great scandals of our time, and a great obstacle to credibility of the Church in the eyes of serious persons who are honestly seeking the truth, is the apparent contradiction between certain teachings of the Church before Vatican II, and certain teachings of Vatican II and the subsequent pontiffs. I have a friend who actually fell away from the Church, and joined the Russian Orthodox on this account. As for me, I have always defended the Council and subsequent magisterial documents, trying to read them with a “hermeneutic of reform” to use Pope Benedict XVI’s important phrase, a hermeneutic of “renewal in the continuity of the one subject-Church which the Lord has given to us” (Benedict XVI, Christmas Address to the Roman Curia, 2005). But documents such as Amoris Laetitia make such a reading very difficult. There are numerous passages in Amoris Laetitia that seem on the face of them to simply contradict previous teachings, rather than reforming and renewing them. I will mention only one example. In ¶161, Pope Francis writes: “Rather than speak absolutely of the superiority of virginity, it should be enough to point out that the different states of life complement one another, and consequently that some can be more perfect in one way and others in another” (AL 161). Contrast those words with the 10th definition of the 24th session of the Council of Trent: “If anyone says that it is not better and more blessed to remain in virginity than to be joined in marriage, let him be anathema.” Such an apparent contradiction, made without any attempt at explanation, without any acknowledgement at all of a solemn definition of an Ecumenical Council, is a scandal in the strictest sense.

Your Eminence, dear Pater Christoph, I hope that this letter, which I have tried to write with reverence as well as parrhesia, will not be taken as a sign of lack of docility on my part. I want to emphasize again that there are many, many things in Amoris Laetitia that I find very beautiful and helpful. The wisdom of an experienced and loving pastor will be a great help to me in my priestly life.

In Corde Jesu,

Pater Edmund


Header image: Titian, Sacred and Profane Love



17 responses to “Amoris Lætitia”

  1. […] the week (and, not coincidentally, one day after he caught us out in a r embarrassing solecism), Pater Edmund Waldstein, O.Cist., published a must-read essay on Amoris laetitia. There are two points we’d make about Pater Waldstein’s essay. First, he begins with a […]

    Like

  2. Thank you. I look forward to hearing of His Eminence’s reply.

    Like

  3. Daniel Koenemann Avatar
    Daniel Koenemann

    Very nice piece. I would love to hear your opinion on Humani Generis 20. It seems to me that Pius overplays his hand a bit here.

    Like

    1. Oh, I think my reflections are in line with Humani Generis 20. “If the Supreme Pontiffs in their official documents purposely pass judgment on a matter up to that time under dispute, it is obvious that that matter, according to the mind and will of the Pontiffs, cannot be any longer considered a question open to discussion among theologians.” That’s quite true. The exceptional case, is when the pope appears teach something contrary to settled teaching.

      Like

  4. Father,

    It seems to me that your impression of non-continuity may be caused, in part, by some things you’re reading into Francis. For instance, where does Francis indicate that one ought “to predict a low level of subjective guilt for objectively evil actions that someone is intending to perform in the future”? I don’t see anywhere in AL that he says mitigating circumstances allow one to remain in objective situations of sin. He says, instead, that discernment must “remain ever open to new stages of growth and to new decisions which can enable the ideal to be more fully realized.”

    On my reading, Pope Francis’ ch. 8 boils down to two points:

    1) Just because someone is in an objective situation of sin, that doesn’t mean the person is fleeing God. The person may be seeking Him (albeit poorly), and this must be acknowledged where it is the case.

    2) The natural law is not a series of rules. It affects life only through the organic judgments of prudence. Therefore, “We have been called to form consciences, not to replace them”—“it is enough simply to apply moral laws to those living in ‘irregular’ situations, as if they were stones to throw at people’s lives.” The goal of discernment is to help people grasp, in a lived way, the “inherent values” that ground the rules: since morality is about living insight into reality, not about fulfilling a checklist.

    That is, we should be as understanding towards the broken as we can be according to the Church’s “solid body of reflection concerning mitigating factors and situations” (which rules out many innovations); and we should help people to achieve an organic, personal grasp of morality.

    Several other points seem worth highlighting:

    1) Francis says “the [moral] law is itself a gift of God which points out the way, a gift for everyone without exception; it can be followed with the help of grace” (295).

    2) Throughout, his definition of prudence is Thomistic. That is, he doesn’t mean it in the more modern sense of “prudential decisions,” but in the all-encompassing sense in which every free act depends on prudence. The source he cites in fn. 350 makes this clear.

    3) In his discussion of culpability in ch. 8, he’s talking about “all those in any ‘irregular situation,’ ” which is really broad (301). So, his statements cannot be particularized for each irregular situation in the same way. He’s not always thinking of the divorced-and-civilly-remarried, and he shouldn’t be interpreted as if he is.

    4) He gives a list of conditions which “must necessarily be present” for discernment: “humility, discretion and love for the Church and her teaching, in a sincere search for God’s will and a desire to make a more perfect response to it.” He further says that a person must be “responsible and tactful” and “not presume to put his or her own desires ahead of the common good of the Church.”

    If these things were remembered, AL would probably be viewed pretty differently.

    (I’d also point out that in fn. 329 he’s speaking of people who are “accepting” the possibility of living as brothers and sisters, not of those who are using “faithfulness-endangerment” as an excuse to reject it.)

    Like

    1. You make some good points, but I don’t agree with every point. A few things:

      Your write: «I don’t see anywhere in AL that he says mitigating circumstances allow one to remain in objective situations of sin. He says, instead, that discernment must “remain ever open to new stages of growth and to new decisions which can enable the ideal to be more fully realized.”» But look at the text right before the bit you quote: “Yet conscience can do more than recognize that a given situation does not correspond objectively to the overall demands of the Gospel. It can also recognize with sincerity and honesty what for now is the most generous response which can be given to God, and come to see with a certain moral security that it is what God himself is asking amid the concrete complexity of one’s limits, while yet not fully the objective ideal.” It seems to me that the natural reading of this is that someone can in good conscience think that continuing to do objectively grave evil will not be a mortal sin.

      « Just because someone is in an objective situation of sin, that doesn’t mean the person is fleeing God.» There are certain kinds of action that cannot be ordered to God as their final end. If someone intends to continue performing such actions, knowing that they are contrary to God’s will, then they are fleeing God. If I set out on a journey to the East, but then take a train toward the West, knowing that that train is going West, then it makes know sense to say “I am going East.”

      «in fn. 329 he’s speaking of people who are “accepting” the possibility of living as brothers and sisters, not of those who are using “faithfulness-endangerment” as an excuse to reject it.» If they truly accept the possibility of living as brothers and sisters what is the purpose of pointing out that “if certain expressions of intimacy are lacking, ‘it
      often happens that faithfulness is endangered and the good of the children suffers.’”?

      Like

  5. Thank you for your gracious reply, Father. I was afraid my comment, written with some speed, may have taken on a “lecturing tone,” which was far from my intention.

    I agree that the passage about conscience you quote is unclear. It does seem like it may be saying that conscience is in the business of authorizing excuses–but that, of course, is no part of the traditional picture of the conscience. So, it seems best to understand it another way, if possible. And I think it can be understood in an orthodox way, in the light of #295: “This is not a ‘gradualness of law’ but rather a gradualness in the prudential exercise of free acts on the part of subjects who are not in a position to understand, appreciate, or fully carry out the objective demands of the law. For the law is itself a gift of God which points out the way, a gift for everyone without exception; it can be followed with the help of grace, even though each human being ‘advances gradually with the progressive integration of the gifts of God and the demands of God’s definitive and absolute love in his or her entire personal and social life.’ ” So he seems to be trying to point out that conscience is not only a faculty that condemns but a faculty that motivates; even a conscience that hasn’t yet entered fully into the light of truth still presses toward the truth it recognizes. This “positivity” of conscience is something that must be remembered when helping someone form his conscience. If a person follows it–so far from keeping him secure in excuses–it ensures that he continues pressing toward truth.

    I agree with your second point, that certain acts have to be morally culpable even in a person of extremely deficient prudence. But since he’s only saying that not “all those in any irregular situation” are fleeing God, some may well be (and necessarily be, by the nature of their situation) with contradicting him. His broadness of statement may, perhaps, be unclear; but it’s not false.

    As for your third point, I confess myself uncertain what fn. 329 was intended to mean. My best guess is that he was trying to point out that the problem of ‘faithfulness-endangerment’ isn’t only an excuse. It’s a real problem that, although of less weight than the moral imperatives, should still be treated seriously. To speak really (really) loosely, the adulterous acts do contribute, in a way, towards certain a good ends; and the couple’s attempt to live chastely would be aided if those good ends could be supplied with other, morally licit, means of support. Alternatively, “certain expression of intimacy” may, in his mind, refer to something other than the marital act and “expressions” opposed to chastity. But I honestly don’t know.

    Like

    1. Carl Kuss, L.C. Avatar
      Carl Kuss, L.C.

      To me logic dictates that the “certain expressions of intimacy” does not refer to marital acts, for it is stipulated that the persons in question understand and accept the possibility of living together as brother and sister; it is absurd to understand this as saying that in spite of understanding and accepting the possibility, they are saying that it really would not be advisable to live consistently as brother and sister. What it is saying is that living as brother and sister such couples do not exclude certain expressions of intimacy, but rather affirm that such expressions are part a not to be shunned part of a relation which is being lived now chastely. The expressions of Pope Francis here are valiant, not disturbing. They form part of Pope Francis’s well thought out campaign against rigorism and its invasive disregard for the sanctuary of conscience..

      Like

      1. Carl Kuss, L.C. Avatar
        Carl Kuss, L.C.

        To me it is quite evident that “certain expressions of intimacy” does not refer to marital acts, for, since it is stipulated that the persons in question understand and accept the possibility of living together as brother and sister; it is absurd to understand this as meaning that in spite of understanding and accepting this possibility, these couples are saying that it really would not be advisable to live coherently as brother and sister. Rather, such couples are telling us that certain expressions of intimacy are not to be excluded from their relation, and that indeed such expressions nurture and lay the groundwork of the essentially chaste relation which the couple now, by definition, have, protecting the bonum prolis and the bonum fidelitatis. The citation of Gaudium et Spes is thus not only intelligible but keenly eloquent, in spite of certain of the critics of AL reminding us, tediously, that the conciliar text is not speaking of the divorced and remarried; indeed it is not speaking of them, but is speaking of an analogous situation, and where there is analogy there is a certain identity. is living, The expressions of Pope Francis are valiant, not disturbing. They form part of Pope Francis’s well-thought-out campaign against rigorism and its invasive disregard for the sanctuary of conscience. They may rub certain people the wrong way, but there I think the Pope shows his valiant spirit.

        [I have taken the liberty to a little editing of the comment made above; I hope that will be forgiven.]

        Like

  6. […] Holy Father without reservation when he teaches what has always and everywhere been taught. Indeed, a Catholic ought to be willing to affirm all of the Holy Father’s teachings, provided that the…. At any rate, one ought to avoid the fundamentally political temptation to deny everything […]

    Like

  7. Carl Kuss, L.C. Avatar
    Carl Kuss, L.C.

    The piece in First Things by Michael Pakaluk regarding the other footnote assumes that expressions of intimacy means sex. Yet it seems that we have in Cardinal Schönborn himself someone who simply does not read it that way (and Pope Francis has told us that Cardinal Schönborn’s hermeneutic in this question represents his own). The false assumption that intimacy means sex affects also determines Pakaluk’s reading of Gaudium et Spes 51: he seems to think that the Council is telling those married couples who have a legitimate reason (founded upon special and difficult circumstances) for interrupting or making less frequent the intimate (sexual) relations of marriage (such a reason as those couples may have who are practicing periodic abstinence from sexual intimacy following the methods of natural family planning) should in fact, doubt that very legitimacy because it contradicts the essential structure and finality of matrimony: the bonum prolis and the bonum fidelitatis. But the whole idea of Gaudium et Spes here is not to call into question that there will be a way–not evidently an easy one–to protect the integrity of marriage in such difficult circumstances, but to encourage couples in such circumstances to find the way that God calls them to. But the existence of such a way implies the existence of expressions of intimacy (not sexual intercourse) through which the marriage will be given flesh. Pakaluk misinterprets the expression bonum prolis in reductivistic and merely biological sense, confusing such an understanding with the “traditional understanding”: thus he rejects the idea that the bonum prolis also includes the welfare and upbringing of children.

    Like

  8. […] my letter to Cardinal Schönborn on Amoris Laetitia I made the following comment on that […]

    Like

  9. […] I envisioned in the reflections on submission to magisterial teaching with which I introduced my letter to Cardinal Schönborn. The case has to do with that category of magisterial teachings with the least authoritative […]

    Like

  10. […] read of the dubia, as I had expressed somewhat similar concerns to those of the four cardinals in my letter to Cardinal Schönborn. Moreover, I had later signed a list of censured propositions drawn up by certain theologians, and […]

    Like

Leave a comment

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.